Elizabeth Anscombe

In the January 1958 issue of Philosophy, British philosopher G. E. M. (Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret鈥斺淓lizabeth鈥) Anscombe (1919-2001) published one of the most important philosophical articles of the twentieth century, 鈥淢odern Moral Philosophy.鈥 (You may recognize Anscombe as the young philosopher who, ten years earlier, bested C. S. Lewis in a debate at the Oxford Socratic Club).

Other than Edmund Gettier鈥檚 1963 piece in Analysis,  arguably no single philosophy article has generated so much discussion and lasting influence. One legacy of 鈥淢odern Moral Philosophy鈥 is Anscombe鈥檚 introduction of the term consequentialism, which has since become the standard way to describe ethical views like utilitarianism, according to which the moral value of an action is a function solely of the consequences produced by it. (Brute facts is another common philosophical term Anscombe introduced here).

But by far the most significant effect of 鈥淢odern Moral Philosophy鈥 was its defining role in the birth of contemporary virtue ethics, as an alternative to the dominant Kantian and utilitarian approaches. (Alasdair MacIntyre鈥檚 , in 1981, was the second key moment).

Of course, there鈥檚 actually nothing new about this movement. It鈥檚 a recovery鈥攁 return to the classical philosophical and theological tradition, especially (for Anscombe herself) to Aristotle. But in 1958 (and in the 1980鈥檚, when I first studied moral philosophy), focusing on virtues and character was new and exciting鈥攁 revolution.

It still is exciting and revolutionary, at least to me. But now, like other revolutions of that era, this one has reached senior status.

Is virtue ethics now old hat?

Has virtue ethics become old and creaky? Irrelevant? Its energy spent or dwindling?

Hardly. It鈥檚 gone mainstream.

Moral philosophers and theologians are actively producing fruitful analyses of a whole range of virtues (and vices), and continue to do exciting work in moral psychology and action theory, neglected areas identified by Anscombe as needing philosophical attention. But taking virtue seriously has moved far beyond philosophy. It鈥檚 now mainstream in the field of psychology (see, for example, Peterson and Seligman鈥檚 massive  and education. In addition, talk of 鈥渉uman flourishing鈥濃攁nother of Anscombe鈥檚 distinctive emphases鈥攏ow pervades all the disciplines.

To some extent, these effects of 鈥淢odern Moral Philosophy鈥 carry a bit of irony. As with her chief philosophical influence, Ludwig Wittgenstein (who called her 鈥渙ld man鈥), Anscombe鈥檚 writing was terse and, dare I say (with appropriately British understatement), 鈥渘ot always as clear as we might wish.鈥 This is evident in the very different interpretations made of her arguments in the article, particularly concerning the notion of moral obligation.

According to Anscombe,

"The concepts of obligation, and duty鈥moral obligation and moral duty, that is to say鈥攁nd of what is morally right and wrong, and of the moral sense of 鈥渙ught,鈥 ought to be jettisoned if this is psychologically possible; because they are survivals, or derivatives from survivals, from an earlier conception of ethics which no longer generally survives, and are only harmful without it."

And what is this earlier conception? 鈥淭he answer is in history: between Aristotle and us came Christianity, with its law conception of ethics.鈥

Anscombe says,

"To have a law conception of ethics is to hold that what is needed for conformity with the virtues . . . is required by divine law. Naturally it is not possible to have such a conception unless you believe in God as a lawgiver; like Jews, Stoics, and Christians. But if such a conception is dominant for many centuries, and then is given up, it is a natural result that the concepts of 鈥渙bligation,鈥 of being bound or required as by a law, should remain though they had lost their root." 

According to Anscombe, the 鈥渕odern鈥 ethical theories of both Kantianism and utilitarianism, with their talk of 鈥渕oral obligation,鈥 unwittingly presuppose what is only valid within the framework of divine law. But since 鈥渨e鈥 no longer believe in a divine lawgiver, she seems to be saying, we should give up on such language. Instead, we should simply focus, as did Aristotle, on virtues.

This is exactly what modern virtue ethicists, following Anscombe, have done.

The irony, however, is that Elizabeth Anscombe herself was a devout Christian, a strong believer in divine law and its expression in the natural law tradition. Indeed, she defended it in print and practiced it in her own life鈥攆rom outspoken and controversial opposition to the bombing of Hiroshima, prior to writing 鈥淢odern Moral Philosophy,鈥 to arrests and imprisonment for non-violent prolife activism as an elderly woman.

So in 1958, was Anscombe arguing, as commonly interpreted, that virtue ethics replace all moral thought based on moral obligation? Or was she employing a kind of modus tollens argument, indirectly commending the importance of acknowledging a divine basis of obligation? (See Julia Driver鈥檚  on "Anscombe" in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.)

This post was originally published with .